And they ask you about the spirit—Say: The spirit is from the affair of my Lord
Human nature has been a central theme of intellectual and mystical
contemplation from ancient times and across civilizations. By virtue of
distinctive traits like rationality, knowledge, speech, and moral
agency, man was considered a world apart from the rest of nature, and
the spirit of man was recognized as something unique and wondrous. In
Islam, knowledge of one’s soul is the point of departure for its
purification and for attaining divine love, given that an authentic life
of piety and altruism emanates from a sanctified soul absorbed in the
remembrance of God.
With the advent of modernity, new philosophical commitments brought
new terminology and novel theories. What most civilizations
traditionally named spirit or soul is often called “mind” today due to
the theological implications of the classical terms.
The branch of modern philosophy that deals with what the medievals
called soul is the philosophy of mind, a field of inquiry that relates
to many critical issues in both academic and public discourse. For
example, is transhumanism—the theory that through science and
technology, humans can evolve beyond current physical limitations and
elude aging or even death—a genuine possibility if there is such thing
as a human soul? Is atheism, which attempts to explain all of reality
through materialism, rendered incoherent if man has an immaterial
intellect? Do human consciousness, thought, and rationality signify the
existence of the soul? With the scientific method as its governing
approach to knowledge, modernity has attempted to unpack man’s inner
mystery through a variety of somewhat contrasting paradigms, such as
neuroscience, Freudian psychoanalysis, behavioral genetics, and
evolutionary psychology.
So much of human culture, society, and even politics hinges on our
awareness of ourselves as human beings and our relationship with the
world we inhabit. How we understand the mind is central to that
awareness.
Historically, Muslim theologians generally espoused an integrative
substance dualism of body and soul. As Syed Naquib al-Attas defines,
“Man has a dual nature, he is both body and soul, he is at once physical
being and spirit.”
While Muslim scholastics deemed the essence of the soul to be a
mysterious divine secret—what the mystic Ibn ʿAjībah (d. 1224/1809)
termed “a luminous, lordly subtlety”—it
was evident that the soul is (a) distinct from the body, though deeply
integrated with it, and (b) the locus of human consciousness. Yet as
spiritual substance, the soul is inaccessible to empirical
investigation: consciousness is located in a realm beyond the
physical—not in mulk, the corporeal world, but in malakūt,
the spiritual world. The question of its artificial replication is for
most theists a nonstarter, since human manipulation is limited to the
physical domain. The possibility of replicating consciousness (or
generally, any feature of the mind) largely emerges from what is termed naturalism—the
view that all things and events in nature can be explained physically,
even if the hard sciences have yet to discover their explanations,
because natural processes take place of their own accord. As an
explanatory idea, naturalism is most often associated with materialism—or physicalism—an ontological position which holds that only “physical matter” really exists.
In Death of the Soul: From Descartes to the Computer, William Barrett has traced the gradual exclusion of mind from intellectual deliberations on reality. The
seventeenth century inaugurated a new science that viewed the world as a
machine, based on a theory of matter that deems physical objects to be
composites of particles in empty space. The mechanism of this
Newtonian science was coupled with John Locke’s famous distinction
between primary and secondary qualities. According to Locke, since
physical objects are merely quantifiable aggregates of molecules, they
have only “primary qualities” like extension and shape, while “secondary
qualities” like color, taste, or sound are absent from the
objects-in-themselves and exist only as sensations in people. What
is “out there” is only the quantitative and measurable. Unsurprisingly,
if quality is generally removed from one’s account of what actually
exists, then the mind with all of its qualitative features is also
susceptible to being reduced to the quantitative brain/body.
The eighteenth century brought another watershed moment with the
skepticism of David Hume, who reduced human experience to a succession
of sense impressions, and moreover considered the “self” to be nothing
more than a bundle of perceptions. Barrett laments, “The I, or ego,
suffered here a blow from which the fragmentation of the Modern Age has
never rescued it. We live in a world where the flow of sensations,
copiously fed to us by all the devices of technology, can virtually turn
the ordinary citizen into a heap of perceptions.” Barrett
notes that Hume’s categorical mistake, though, was to search for the
self in objective sense-data rather than to recognize his own
subjectivity in that search. Yet subsequent thinkers were captivated by
Hume’s ideas; and as technology and the hard sciences rapidly advanced,
materialism would emerge as a reigning paradigm for modern science.
Nevertheless, in the eyes of many philosophers of mind, materialism has
now reached an insurmountable quandary in the question of consciousness.
Physicalist Theories About the Mind
Physicalist theories that attempt to explain mental states include
eliminative materialism, behaviorism, identity theory, and
functionalism.
In light of the continued success and explanatory power of modern physics, physiology, and neuroscience, eliminative materialism [EM]
denies the existence of psychological states (sensations, thoughts,
feelings, etc.): notions like “John is in pain” and “Fred enjoys vanilla
ice cream” are eliminated and replaced by “John’s brain is in neural
state X” and “Fred’s brain is in neural state Y.” For eliminativists
like Paul Churchland, the commonsense view that mental states are
real—what he terms “folk psychology”—is simply a theory, and
one that is devoid of explanatory power. So he argues that it is a false
theory: its history of failure to provide scientifically useful
explanations leads to the conclusion that the mental states of folk
psychology are merely illusions. However, opponents of this view argue
that (a) our psychological states do not themselves comprise a theory but require a
theory (or metaphysical worldview) to explain them; and (b) EM as a
theory proves incoherent and self-refuting, insofar as its claims that
it is true, and that folk psychology is false, reveal intentionality, itself a profoundly salient state of the mind. Truth claims are propositional attitudes that EM denies. Acceptance of EM presupposes folk psychology, since EM rejects notions like “acceptance.”
Another materialist/physicalist theory of mind is philosophical behaviorism [PB],
according to which psychological states are logically equivalent to
“dispositions” of behavior: pain is not a subjective reality, but is
only the tendency to wince or cry or say “Ouch!,” etc. To justify PB,
proponents adduce as evidence the strong connection between mental
states and behavior, which for them can readily be explained as a
connection between behavioral dispositions and behavior. To be
“in pain” is to be “disposed” to certain behaviors (crying, wincing, …);
to be “happy” is to be “disposed” to certain other behaviors (smiling,
laughing, …); and so forth.
PB is also supported by the Vienna Circle’s theory of verificationism in the philosophy of language, a theory that was central to the Circle’s broader philosophy of logical positivism,
a form of empiricism that denied the possibility of metaphysics. This
early twentieth-century group of philosophers and scientists in Vienna,
Austria, argued that the meaning of any statement is rooted in its
method of verification, and verification was limited to sense-data: if a
statement could not be verified empirically, it did not have rational
(or “cognitive”) meaning. Thus, some PB proponents argued that if
sensory observation is the only avenue of ascertaining the meaning of a
proposition, then private mental states can be translated to observable
behavior without losing meaning. Most philosophers, though, do not
subscribe to verificationism, which has been almost unanimously
discarded in the philosophy of language for several reasons, such as the
theory’s incoherence—verificationism itself cannot be empirically
verified.Moreover,
critics of PB point out that PB is demonstrably flawed, for it is
conceivable that a person could have rich and changing mental states yet
refrain from any behavior at all. Not
all pain is expressed through crying or wincing, and not all happiness
through smiling and laughing. And quite often, a person’s behavior is
informed by innumerable mental states (beliefs, emotions, desires,
motives, …) that are near impossible to reduce to algorithms of
corresponding physical behavior.
Both EM and PB have generally proven untenable as physicalist
theories of mind, leading most materialists to embrace what is termed identity theory [IT].
IT is based on the idea that conceptual differences do not necessarily
entail actual distinction between different entities, and that empirical
investigation can confirm their shared identity. So, according to
proponents like J.J.C. Smart, just as “water” and “H2O,” or
“lightning” and “atmospheric electrical discharge,” are conceptually
different yet empirically identical, so too are mental states
empirically identical to physical brain states despite the conceptual
difference between them. While
subjective, first-person mental states may seem to be vastly different
from objective, third-person neuronal states, IT holds that empirical
investigation has shown them to be identical. IT
theorists do not propose merely that mental states are related to or
interact with brain states—many forms of dualism will admit as much—but
that they are the same thing. IT theorists also do not deny the
existence of mental states as EM theorists do. According to IT,
experiences of the mind are real, yet they are reducible to operations
of the brain, since the two are in fact identical; mental states are physical
brain states. The particular feeling I get when my finger gets jammed
by the door is held to be identical with some specific activity in my
brain (such as “c-fiber firing,” or activation of the neural pathways
associated with pain). Even though they differ in sense, “pain” and “c-fiber firing” refer to one and the same reality, so pain is nothing more than c-fiber firing.
One cogent objection to IT is to note the philosophical leap from
correlation to identity. Empirical study has certainly demonstrated
correlation between, for example, pain and c-fiber firing. Yet as Roger
Scruton notes, to assert “identity” would entail that if a c-fiber
associated with pain were completely removed from someone’s body and
then stimulated in a laboratory, someone or something would be in pain,
which is patently false. This
objection could also be framed within the principle that if A and B are
identical, each will have all the properties of the other. Yet the conscious experience of pain is to hurt, while c-fiber firing has no property of hurting.
The objection is related to Saul Kripke’s linguistic discussion on
“rigid designators,” or terms that denote the same object in any
possible world. For
IT to be true, statements like “Pain is identical to c-fiber firing”
would have to be true in every possible world, meaning both sides of the
sentence would have to be rigid designators. Yet as the above example
shows, we can easily conceive of a world in which c-fiber firing exists
without pain, and in which pain exists without c-fiber firing; hence,
c-fiber firing is not a rigid designator of pain. In other words, mental
experiences and brain activity are simply two different kinds of
things, even if strong correlations between the two are discovered.
Another related objection is that IT obviates “multiple realization,” or
the realization of the same mental states in animals with different
neurophysiology: if pain is identical to c-fiber firing, then animals
whose pain is found to be associated with the firing of d-fibers (or
e-fibers, or f-fibers, etc.) could not in fact experience pain, since
pain is identical to the firing of c-fibers.
Based on the multiple realizability objection and other concerns, most materialists came to embrace the theory of functionalism,
which is based on the notion that a thing is defined by its function
rather than by its substance. Thus, what is conventionally called a
“mental state” is only some function in the organism’s
behavior—specifically, a connection between environmental input and
behavioral output. Multiple realizability can be accommodated: human
“c-fiber firing” executes the same function as cat “d-fiber
firing,” and “experiencing pain” is but an internal mechanism that
carries out that particular function. And a “function” is described by
the network of causal relations between environmental stimuli (input)
and bodily behavior (output). For example, the function of pain is
explained by the connection between a door slamming on one’s finger or a
cat’s paw (input) and yelling “Ouch!” or a high-pitched feline sound
(output). The function might also incorporate other “mental states,”
that is, other functions that are internally connected. So in the
example of pain, the input of one’s finger being slammed by a door would
be connected to “anger,” which itself is but a function with its own
algorithmic connections. The language of “mind” that we humans
conventionally use is simply a convenient way of expressing functions. Thus, as a theory of mind, functionalism allows for what John Searle has called “Strong Artificial Intelligence” (Strong AI), or the notion that a computer could have genuine mental states, since theoretically it could be programmed to have the same functions exhibited
by humans, the same functional connections between stimuli and output.
Related to this is Alan Turing’s famous “Turing Test,” which holds that a
machine will be deemed intelligent (and conscious) “if it acts so like
an ordinary person in certain respects that other ordinary people can’t
tell… that it isn’t one.”
The Intractability of Consciousness
What functionalism excludes of consciousness, however, are essential features like qualia and intrinsic intentionality.
Mental states involve what philosophers call qualia, or the way it feels to
be in pain, to enjoy ice cream, or to see red. And certain qualia are
features of all consciousness, human or animal. As Thomas Nagel has
argued, a scientist who gains mastery of all there is to know about
echolocation in bats, of complete bat neuroscience, and of all the
functional connections of bat behavior, would still not know “what it’s like to be a bat.” There is a first-person feel to that reality that no third-person account can provide. Frank Jackson has made a similar qualia argumentwith
color: if a scientist who had never seen color were forced to
investigate nature from within a black-and-white room, and learned
everything about the physical basis of seeing color—“everything in completed physics,
chemistry, and neurophysiology, and all there is to know about the
causal and relational facts consequent upon all this, including of
course functional roles”—she would undoubtedly gain new knowledge of the
world were she to go out and see red for the first time. Specifically,
as Jackson explains, “she will realize how impoverished her conception
of the mental life of others has been all along.”
Some identity theorists respond that, as IT asserts, the conceptual
distinction between qualia and scientific knowledge of related brain
processes itself is not evidence of their actual distinction. Yet
proponents of knowledge arguments reply that the first-person subjective
experience of qualia is still undeniable, and physicalist descriptions
of objective neuronal activity leave that out. Knowledge arguments like
these demonstrate that qualia are real, based on the categorical
distinction between first-person subjective experience and third-person
description. Functionalism is therefore false, and Strong AI incoherent.
A computer programmed to mimic human response to stimuli clearly lacks
qualia.
Mental states also have intentionality, or a directedness towards something (that is, they are about something): we can think about the universe, or about history, or even about our
consciousness, etc. Based on intentionality, John Searle has formulated
a thought experiment called “The Chinese Room” that argues against
functionalism and strong AI.
If one were to imagine a person who does not understand Chinese, locked
in a room with a rule book (effectively, a computer program) that lists
correct answers to questions in Chinese; who receives those questions
as input from someone outside the room; and who, based on the rule book,
provides perfectly correct answers as output back to the person
outside, it remains true that the man in the room still does not
understand Chinese, even though the Turing Test was passed successfully
from the vantage of the person outside the room. The man in the room is
akin to a computer that is programmed to give correct answers to
questions in Chinese: neither the man nor the computer understands Chinese. While there is extrinsic intentionality in the form of “function,” or giving correct output in response to input, the intrinsic intentionality of
understanding Chinese is notably absent. And intrinsic intentionality
is a quintessential, necessary property of thought and consciousness.
Intentionality proves to be one of the remarkable features of
consciousness that reveals its obstinacy to physicalist reduction or
dismissal. Meaning is mysteriously grounded in the purely mental. As
Edward Feser notes, anything physical that exhibits meaning, such as a
word or a picture, does so only because of mental agents designating it
as meaningful—its intentionality is derived and not intrinsic. In and
of themselves, words, pictures, or computer pixels are merely marks on a
surface. It is only mind that gives those marks meaning. And like ink
marks on paper, brain processes are physical entities/processes
inherently void of meaning. Yet the concepts and propositions that
comprise thought are undeniably non-physical, abstract, and universal.
Feser comments:
Had there been no human beings, the proposition there are no human beings
would have been true, even though there would then have been no
“sentence in the head” for that proposition to be identical to. Had
there been no physical world at all, the proposition there is no physical world
would have been true, even though there would then have been no
physical entity of any sort for that proposition to be identical to….
[W]hen the mind grasps a concept or proposition, there is clearly a
sense in which that concept or proposition is in the mind; but if these
things are in the mind and yet… cannot be in the brain, it would seem to
follow that the mind cannot be identified with the brain, or for that
matter with anything material.
“The robust features of human consciousness cannot be dismissed
in philosophical deliberation, and philosophical deliberation cannot be
forced to fit into the narrow assumptions of scientism.”
Indeed, despite the celebrated achievements of the physical
sciences, materialism as an all-encompassing worldview has gradually
faded, if not altogether failed, in light of those features of the world
that cannot be reduced to physical matter—morals, values, purpose,
meaning, rationality, aesthetics, and—arguably the most recalcitrant to
naturalist reduction—consciousness. The robust features of human
consciousness cannot be dismissed in philosophical deliberation, and
philosophical deliberation cannot be forced to fit into the narrow
assumptions of scientism. These robust features of consciousness, or
conscious states, include:
- Sensation or sentient awareness, whether of external things
(through sense-data: sight, smell, taste, hearing, and touch), or of
internal states (such as hunger, thirst, pain, and pleasure). Emotions,
too—anger, sadness, joy, empathy, and the like—are sensed internally. In
fact, one’s very existence is apprehended directly by consciousness.
- Intellection,
including the direct unmediated grasp of first principles, or mediated
reasoning through the deduction of conclusions from premises. Noteworthy
in this regard is the very foundation of human reasoning: simple
apprehension, or the abstraction of universals from particulars, so as
to form and understand concepts.
- Belief, or the internal assent to a proposition and the act of regarding it as true or false, likely or unlikely.
- Desire or wanting.
- Memory.
- Will or choice, meaning the faculty that selects between alternatives so as to act accordingly.
- Motive, meaning the impetus that propels a person towards or away from an action.
Many philosophers would include intuition, insight, and what is termed “common sense.”
All of these features are integrated in the centered self and
together inform one’s choice, agency, and experience. Furthermore, human
consciousness has the unique property of “awareness of one’s very consciousness”—the
profound capacity of self-reflection, wherein consciousness faces
itself and “sees” its own awareness, apprehension, realization, and
sapience. All of the above features of consciousness are experienced
internally and privately by the subject: they are first-person,
subjective, and have an undeniable immediacy for the individual. They
cannot be described in the third-person or objective language used for
what is physical, even if a correlation between mental states and
physical states/events in the brain is empirically found.
As we attempt to understand the mind, should we weigh the arguments of philosophy above the theories of science?
A final consideration for the uniqueness of “mind” and its
distinctiveness from the physical domain is the unity and simplicity of
consciousness. This is a principal rational argument for substance
dualism put forth by the Muslim theologian Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī (d.
606/1209) in his treatise on the soul, and
different versions of it have been used by Descartes, Leibniz, Kant,
and others since. Mental awareness is unified and indivisible, expressed
by the singular “I” that represents the individual. The brain, however,
is composite. It is a collection of physical parts organized in a
certain way. And if a composite substance were the locus of
consciousness, then each part of the aggregate would have a part of
consciousness. Yet consciousness, as denoted by the pronoun “I,” is not
divisible into parts. It is what philosophers call “simple.” William
Hasker comments, “A person’s being aware of a complex fact cannot consist of parts of the person being aware of parts of the fact [emphasis his]. A conjunction of partial awarenesses does not add up to a total awareness.” Likewise, as David Barnett contends, “[F]or any pair of conscious beings, it is impossible for the pair itself to be conscious”; and this is true only because consciousness is simple, while any pair (or group of parts) is composite.
The soul, however, is simple indeed. And it is
the foundation and basis of the spiritual life of man. The implications
of its denial are quite grave, since it is the soul that apprehends
meaning, purpose, and virtue. The theologians and mystics of Islam held
it to be a secret of the Divine, for only the soul is capable of
knowledge—of oneself, of fellow man, of society, of the cosmos, and of
its Creator. And only the soul is capable of love. Among its properties
are to seek, yearn, and long for goodness, for truth, for beauty, for
intimacy, and ultimately for perfection. The enterprise of scientific
discovery itself presupposes this immaterial orientation to these
immaterial, transcendental realities: the scientist is impelled by a passion to discover what is true, and deems that pursuit good.
Metaphysics accommodates transcendentals, as it accommodates
consciousness. At bottom, it would seem that consciousness remains
intractable to ontological reduction or elimination. While the human
body can be described to a great extent in the language of physics and
biochemistry, the human spirit cannot. It must be something else.